четверг, 4 апреля 2019 г.

Developing a theory of mind at four years

Developing a speculation of reason at four historic period hypothesis of Mind is a term introduced by Premack and Woodruff, (1978) it is considered the ability to infer the current rational state of a nonher(prenominal)s, their beliefs and desires (Gazzaniga, Ivry, Mangun, 2009). surmisal of psyche is vital in our chthonicstanding that others knowledge may differ from our own, it eitherows one to manipulate and constitute the actions and contemplations of a nonher in hurt of theoretical and intentional states. As such, we are able to surmise the mental states of others although they may not communicate them with visible cues, such as what they may be thinking or feeling, as well as the ability to distinguish between heartyity and belief. One of the major current debates within give awaymental psychology is centred approximately the get hold of that a opening of sound judgment does not evolve until the board of 4. Although many agree with the claim there are c ountless theorists who believe that a speculation of look is innate therefore it must be present at birth (Fodor, 1992). This essay depart be assessing contributing research towards this debate by looking at reason for and against the claim in order to make an informed decision according to supporting research.One of the most effective ways to rise for a opening of mind in younker children is through the false-belief line of work, as passing the task indicates that the child is aware that others may befool incorrect beliefs abtaboo the world. Wimmer and Perner (1983) found, from their unexpected transfer test, that a amply developed possible action of mind does not appear before the age of 3 to 4 years. In this test infants were told to watch a scene in which a character, Maxi places chocolate in a drawer and walks away. While he is away his mother takes out the chocolate and grates some of it onto a cake, places it elsewhere then leaves. Maxi then returns and the experi menter asks where will Maxi look for the chocolate? Results found that children above the age of 5 had no problem attributing to Maxi a false belief. The teaching was later repeated to children under the age of 4, when it was found that children under the age of around 3.7 years failed to answer questions correctly. Thus this provides strong evidence that a surmise of mind does not develop until around 4 years of age.Another guileless experiment by Baron-Cohen et al (1985) was the Sally-Anne task where the experimenter had adopted analogous characteristics uptaked originally by Wimmer and Perner (1983) and time-tested Autistic children, normal children and those suffering from Downs syndrome for the presence of a Theory of Mind. It was found that the majority of normal and Downs syndrome children answered all questions correctly whereas autistic children found it difficult to comprehend what had happened and tended to answer incorrectly. Although Baron- Cohen et al were testi ng for a theory of mind in Downs syndrome and Autistic children, it should be noted that normal children and Downs syndrome children both appear to nourish a theory of mind hence they would pass the task at 4 years old. An autistic soulfulness however would not have a theory of mind as their minds do not make for in the same way as a normal child, therefore one may suggest that a theory of mind does appear at 4 years but not for tribe with autism.A further piece of evidence lies with Avis Harris who tested the universality of the false-belief task in their study of the Baka children of Cameroon. The Baka is a traditional, hunting and gathering, non literate society where none of the adults or children can read or have been schooled. using the original false-belief task, Avis Harris tested 34 children aged between 3-5 years. Findings were similar to those in Western countries. However the results of this study shows flexibility in the age in which theory of mind develops. It i s not necessarily 4 years within the Baka community which implies that there may not be universality in the age at which theory of mind appears to be present the age is not 4 years it is in point between 3 and 5.Another researcher who has tested for universality in theory of mind is Astington (1996) who gave the false-belief test to Quechua children in Peru, and Tainae children of New Guinea. The results were very incompatible with those from Western countries. Young children and even adolescents could not recognise false-beliefs in others, hence no theory of mind at the age of 4. This provides strong evidence of cultural variation, as the task has consistently proved that children aged 4 are able to answer correctly within most Western countries and this is still likely to be the case if ever replicated.It may however, be considered unbefitting to impose our Western false-belief task on people who have their own practises and teachings within their societies. This does not pisse d other cultures have no misgiving of the mind, they may simply have their own means of perceiving others minds. Hence, children of other cultures and countries may have a theory of mind at the age of 4 we perhaps take up to conduct research of a different method in such societies rather than the false-belief task.Due to the great deal of research in support of the claim that theory of mind appears around the age of 4, psychologists have spot up with theories to explain why this the happens to be the case. The imitational Deficit theory, also known as the theory-theory suggests that children develop beliefs or theories nearly other people, revise them and use them in a similar to manner to how we use scientific theories. As such, by using these theories, children are able to make predictions about new evidence, to look evidence, and to explain evidence (Gopnik, 2003).The theory-theory explanation is essentially a constructivist account as a rational saying of the mind occurs by means of everyday theoretical constructs. Infants instigate with an initial primitive understanding of the mind, they garner data through interaction with the world and others around them which leads to a theory change and thus the maturation of a mature theory of mind at the age of 4 (Gopnik Wellman, 1994).Now looking at evidence against the claim, we must firstly take a look at theories and research which suggests that theory of mind does not in fact develop at 4 years. Problems with evidence for the claim are pointed out by researchers and are noted below.Theory of mind faculty is a theory which essentially goes against the claim that children do not develop a theory of mind until the age of 4. Fodor (1983) originally mentioned innate mental modules thus, in contrast to the theory-theory approach, many theorists have agreed with Fodor and argue that a psychological understanding of the mind is achieved via the computations of an innate mental module (Wellman, 2002). Resea rchers such as Fodor (1992) and Leslie (1987) have all come to a similar accord that there is an individual theory of mind module which creates depictions of human activity in terms of mental attitudes toward specific events (domain specific cognition).Evidence for the theory of mind module and against the theory theory is when researchers conducted theory of mind research on individuals with autism. They proposed that autistic children have impairment on their theory of mind module leading to inability to construe people in terms of mental states i.e. mind blindness (Leslie, 1987 Baron-Cohen et al 1985). However, as we established earlier, this may be due to the fact that autistic people do not have the same functioning of the mind as normal people and thus may have nothing to do with a module.Theory-theory has also been challenged by many researchers as there is over- confidence on false-belief tests. Lewis Osinnate(p)e (1990), for lesson made the point that children can misunde rstand the question being posed. Furthermore, Lewis, Freeman, Hagestadt Douglas (1994) stated that children may fail to understand and integrate key elements of the story.Another critique of the theory-theory is that there have been vast amounts of research of a theory of mind before the age of four. Early theorists, argue that children perform better in naturalistic environs for example Dunn (1988) provided a clear analysis of young childrens understanding of other family members desires, intentions and emotions. However one may argue that this is not actually evidence of a theory of mind, rather it is linked with developmental abilities, it does not mean that a theory of mind is acquired at this stage.It has also been found that children have other earlier (before the age of 4) abilities such as deception (Lewis, Stanger Sullivan, 1989), communicative abilities (Butterworth Jarrett, 1991) and pretence (Leslie, 1987).Numerous researchers have criticised tests such as the false -belief test. De Gelder (1987), for example pointed out that it is known that autistic children have difficulty with pretend play. Therefore, using dolls to represent in truth people may cause them some difficulties. However Leslie and Frith (1987) repeated the same study using real children and obtained similar findings. Furthermore, despite criticisms, false-belief tests have been replicated and the findings supported by many other researchers (Perner, Leekam Wimmer 1987 Gopnik Astington 1988).Mitchell (1996) agreed with the traditional nativistic account of theory of mind. He believed theory of mind had to be present at birth. Mitchells view was that everybody is born with a theory of mind and a reality criterion and young children fail theory of mind tasks as they are guided by the reality criterion. He also emphasised on the reliance of reality with false belief tasks when making judgments. It does not mean young people are unequal to(p) of false belief, it simply suggests that the reality criterion is more dominant. Evidence for Mitchells theory takes form in a modified version of the deceptive box test (Mitchell Lacohee, 1991) originally created by Perner, Leekam Wimmer (1987). In the modified version, 63% of children answered correctly compared with 23% in the standard version.Both of the above theories have been deemed as plausible accounts of the theory of mind in children. However there does not seem to be adequate evidence against the claim. As theory of mind has been defined as the ability to understand others beliefs, this has not been seen to occur until the age of 4 (Perner, 1991). Another significant point is that although early abilities may be precursors to a real theory of mind, it does not mean that the change after 4 years does not exist. Gopnik, Slaughter Meltzoff (1994) named four conceptual changes in the development of a theory of mind which provided evidence that a in full developed theory of mind does not appear until the a ge of 4.A child showing signs of deception, communicative abilities and pretence should even be considered as irrelevant information when studying the theory of mind. Perner (1991) went on to say that pretence, deception etc may be over interpreted. After all, other developmental abilities are each to their own, their presence does not necessarily have to relate to a theory of mind.On balance it would be fair to state that a fully developed mature theory of mind does not appear before the age of 4 and there is not sufficient evidence to backup claims that say otherwise. Although, the majority of evidence relies heavily upon false-belief tasks, the task has been proved to be accurate and reliable. Additionally, Wellman, Cross Watsons meta-analysis (2001) showed that children around 4 years 0 months performed above chance on the false-belief task. They also found that the results were consistent across the period analysed and were not any different for earlier studies than later one s. This provides extremely strong evidence of a theory of mind at the age of 4 compared with zipper evidence against the claim. It would therefore be appropriate to accept the claim that a theory of mind appears around the age of 4 years and this is extremely strong evidence in support of this claim.Astington, J. (1996). what is theoretical about the childs theory of mind?a Vygotskain view of its development. In P. Carruthers, P. K. Smith (Eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind (p. 401). Cambridge Cambridge University Press.Avis, J., Harris, P. (1991). Belief-Desire Reasoning among Baka ChildrenEvidence for a Universal Conception of Mind. Child emergence , 62, 460-467.Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M., Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a theory of mind. scholarship , 37-46.Butterworth, G., Jarrett, N. (1991). What minds have in common is space Spatial mechanisms serving joint visual attention in infancy. British journal of teachingal Psychology , 9 (1), 55-72.Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Masachusetts MIT Press.Chomsky, N. (1986). The Leading Ideas of the minimalist Programme. In H. L. Zeljko Boskovic (Ed.), Minimalist Syntax The Essential Readings (pp. 2-4). Oxford Blackwell Publishing.De Gelder, B. (1987). Discussion on not having a theory of mind. Cognition , 285-290.Dunn, J. (1988). The beginnings of social understanding. Harvard University Press.Fodor, J. (1992). A theory of the childs theory of mind. Cognition , 283-296.Fodor, J. A. (1992). A theory of the childs theory of mind. Cognition , 283-296.Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind an essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press.Gazzaniga, M. S., Ivry, R. B., Mangun, G. R. (2009). Cognitive NeuroscienceThe Biology of the Mind. London W. W. Norton Company Ltd.Gopnik, A. (2003). The Theory Theory as an Alternative to the Innateness Hypothesis. In L. M. Antony, N. Hornstein (Eds.), Chomsky and his Critics (pp. 238-254). Oxford Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Gopnik, A., Astington, J. W. (1988). Childrens mind of Representational Change and Its Relation to the Understanding of dishonorable Belief and the Appearance-Reality Distinction. Child Development , 26-37.Gopnik, A., Wellman, H. (1994). The theory theory. In L. Hirschfield, S. Gelman (Eds.), Domain specificity in culture and cognition (pp. 257-293). New York Cambridge University Press.Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation The origins of theory of mind. Psychological Review , 412-426.Leslie, A. M., Frith, U. (1988). Autistic childrens understanding of seeing, knowing and believing. British Journal of Developmental Psychology , 315-324.Lewis, C., Osborne, A. (1990). triad Year-Olds Problem with False Belief Conceptual Deficit or Linguistic Artifact? Child Development , 1514-1519.Lewis, C., Freeman, N. H., Hagestadt, C., Douglas, H. (1994). Narrative access and production in preschoolers false belief reasoning. . Cognitive Development , 397-424.Lewis, M., Stanger, C., Sulli van, M. W. (1989). Deception in 3-year-olds. Developmental Psychology , 439-443.Meltzoff, A. N. (2002). Imitation as a Mechanism of Social CognitionOrigins of Empathy, Theory of Mind, and the Representation of Action. In U. Goswami (Ed.), Blackwells Handook of Childhood Cognitive Development (pp. 6-25). Oxford Blackwell Publishers Ltd.Mitchell, P. (1996). Acquiring a Conception of Mind. East Sussex Psychology Press.Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Learning, development, and conceptual change. Cambridge The MIT Press.Perner, J., Leekam, S. R., Wimmer, H. (1987). Three-year-olds difficulty with false belief The case for a conceptual deficit. British Journal of Developmental Psychology , 125-137.Piaget, J. (1929). The childs conception of the world. New York Routledge Kegan Paul Ltd.Piaget, J. (1999). The Psychology of Intelligence (2 ed.). (M. Percy, D. E. Berlyne, Trans.) London Rputledge and Kegan and Paul Ltd.Premack, D., Woodruff, G. (1978). chimpanz ee problem-solving a test for comprehension. Science , 532-535.Wellman, H. M. (2002). Understanding the Psychological World Developing a Theory of Mind. In U. Goswami (Ed.), Blackwell Handbook of Childhood Cognitive Development (pp. 167-187). Oxford Blackwell Publishing.Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., Watson, J. (2001). Meta-Analysis of Theory of Mind DevelopmentThe Truth about False Belief. Child Development , 72 (3), 655-684.Wimmer, H., Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young childrens understanding of deception. Cognition , 103-128.

Комментариев нет:

Отправить комментарий